July 17, 2012

Why I Became Vegan (Part 2/4)


II. The Question(s) of Ethics

When people ask, or, more often, demand, to know why I became vegan, an immediate (but ultimately inadequate) response would be “for ethical reasons.” I can generally make myself understood to other people when I evoke ethics, but because it is not the whole truth, it is not the response I like to give.

It is not the whole truth because it dangerously grants vegans and vegetarians a kind of “purity” or moral superiority over other people. In fact, this is a common theme amongst many vegans and vegetarians, and it is difficult to think of anything more agitating to me personally than when “fellow” vegans think that they know what is “right” or “good” and that, therefore, everyone who doesn’t follow their practice is “wrong” or “evil.” In this formulation, veganism/vegetarianism ceases to be an ethical practice and becomes an ideology. This is a form of veganism that deserves to be criticized. By saying this, I do not mean that the ethical question should be dismissed, or that it is dismissible. But it is imperative that vegans and vegetarians stop producing such dogmatic claims to absolute moral truth.

For this reason, I want to begin to unwork some of the more problematic assumptions embedded in ideological veganism/vegetarianism. I would argue instead that ethical justifications for veganism are often either misunderstood or, quite frankly, insipid—that they can, and indeed do, work against the political relevance of being vegan. Saying this may put me at odds with many vegans, and it may seem patently absurd to meat-eaters. This is understandable. However, I hope I offer a gift that “ethical vegans” may come to appreciate, and, furthermore, something of a response to the perennial question of the meat-eating reader—a response that will serve to generate critical thought rather than end it.

First, we must ask, What is “ethics”? In the previous section, I noted that becoming vegan greatly increased my happiness. For this reason, the decision could be considered “ethical,” if when we say “ethics” we use Spinoza’s well-known definition of ethics as an induction into what constitutes “happy life,” that is to say an intellectually flourishing life.

For Spinoza, to ask, What is an ethical life? is the same as asking, What is a happy life? or, What does it mean for me to be happy? Thus, Spinoza wrestled the practice of ethics from the starchy domains of morality and philosophy and returned it to its proper place, praxis. Ethics is not dependent on the expectations placed upon the subject by the various political or religious institutions or organizations to which she belongs, or to which she is said to belong, or to which she is told she must belong, or to which she is made to belong (though, realistically speaking, this is not to say that the two are unrelated for most people). Ethics pertains, simply enough, to happiness. Of course, this is not actually a definition qua definition (that is, in the final, conclusive sense of the word “definition”). Spinoza’s definition simply adds a new density to the way we think ethics and, more importantly, the way we do ethics, by focusing on the question of happiness, which we are now invited to consider along with the question of ethics.

But here we are also confronted by the unique limitations of ethics as they are currently theorized in modernity, especially in the analytic tradition of the English-speaking West. Any given ethical problem, when broached in a university classroom or by armchair ethicists, is practically required to present itself to us fundamentally as a calculable, controllable choice between two (or more) actions. This is a way of practicing ethics that I reject, because, to put it frankly, this brand of ethics rejects me—it rejects my specificity as a spatiotemporally singular being whose daily circumstances and interactions cannot be reduced to a formula; it rejects me and you and, indeed, everyone as historical agents who live in a dis-ordered world but are nevertheless called upon to make decisions (sometimes invisible decisions) every day.

Jacques Derrida’s notion of undecidability is crucial, then, as it relates, especially in his later writings, to the ethical question. An ethical life cannot be reduced to a single, one-time choice between clear opposites, but is in the form of a continuous choice, or, better yet, a continuous affirmation or negation in the context of constantly shifting pressures and determinants. It is therefore wrong to say that veganism is the termination or conclusion of dietary ethics; it rather denotes a position or, to put it less concretely (and therefore more truthfully), an embodied sensibility or ethical sensitivity to the problematic of human-animal relation. Because happiness, like ethics, cannot be a quantifiable operation, the ethical imperative is not to make the correct decision based on pre-existing categories of “the good”; rather, the ethical imperative is produced by the choices and circumstances that present themselves to us.