July 4, 2012

The Fragile Ethics of Testimony (Part 8/10)


V.1
Critiques of Agamben’s Remnants of Auschwitz

Agamben’s book is a thoughtful and, for the most part, meticulously argued work, a moving contribution to the discourses of continental philosophy, political theory, ethics, and Holocaust studies. Agamben carefully integrates survivors’ testimonies and critical theory into a complex and thoroughly engaging reflection on the place of Auschwitz in the cultural memory of the postmodern West and with regard to individual responsibility. Above all, Remants of Auschwitz is a brave work that refuses to retreat from the most difficult questions regarding the extermination, refining along the way theories of subjectivity and political power in order to found a fragile ethical imperative for the post-Auschwitz world.

However, Agamben’s book has not avoided, and indeed should not avoid, criticism for some of its more problematic aspects. In his monograph on Agamben, Leland de la Durantaye calls Remnants of Auschwitz both Agamben’s “most daring” and “most flawed” book, a paradoxical statement that summarizes the majority response to the book in American academia.[i] Largely, the negative response to the book focuses on Agamben’s method, which, in the eyes of some critics, made a paradigm out of the Muselmann that ignores the historical context and material conditions of the camp. And while Durantaye agrees with other reviewers of this work that Agamben stretches the credibility of his method by using the Muselmann as a confirmation of his analysis of the homo sacer, an assessment with which I am personally inclined to agree, he also argues that the shortcomings of Agamben’s paradigmatic approach should not totally nullify the value of the book.[ii] Therefore, though Durantaye sides with several readers who have noted its fundamental problems, his close reading is generally sympathetic and goes some way toward correcting some of the more egregious misreadings of some of Agamben’s more hostile interlocutors.

To repeat, the negative response to this book largely focuses on Agamben’s paradigmatic method rather than Agamben’s conclusions or the content of the book. For example, Neil Levi and Michael Rothberg, in an otherwise largely positive review, share the assessment that Agamben’s scope is simultaneously too narrow and too broad—too narrow because he focuses solely on the Muselmann as the key to reading all testimony, and too broad because, by employing the Muselmann as a transhistorical paradigm, he runs the risk of forgetting the specific historical and material circumstances of the camps.[iii] Similarly, Nicholas Chare mourns the loss of context in Agamben’s careful selection among several survivors’ accounts, contending that Agamben’s overlooks the essential materiality of the language of testimony, and questions Agamben’s “unnecessary” emphasis on the Muselmann as the ethical center of all testimony, noting that this figure is “an extreme example of a more general process.”[iv] (61) Catherine Mills, additionally, points out that Agamben’s paradigmatic method comes dangerously close to treating the atrocities of the camp and the current biopolitical norm of modern government as if they were the inevitable results of various traditions or concepts of Western thought rather than terrible mutations of such traditions and concepts.[v]

A more extreme form of the same critique can be found in J. M. Bernstein’s response to the book, in which he argues that Agamben “aestheticizes” witnessing to the extent that his fragile ethical imperative borders on “pornography.”[vi] In the ensuing discussion, which tenuously links the “extraordinary and excruciating” war photography by James Nachtwey to Agamben’s book, Bernstein vaguely concludes, “[T]here is something photographic about Agamben’s practice of one by one removing from consideration the historical, the political and above all the moral frames through reference to which some understanding of the meaning of the Muselmann might be achieved.”[vii] I cannot help but feel that Bernstein would be well-served by another, slower reading of Agamben’s book and a more critical examination of his own terms. It is simply not sufficient to posit “something photographic”—much less something “pornographic”—about Agamben’s work without a much more rigid attempt to theorize photography or pornography as technologically mediated social categories. In fact, I would argue that Bernstein, with his deliberately provocative vocabulary and his repeated insistence that he has exposed some hidden perversity in Agamben’s work, comes much closer to producing “pornography” than Agamben. Agamben’s paradigmatic approach, though obviously problematic, is neither aesthetic nor pornographic in even the loosest senses of the terms.


[i] Leland de la Durantaye, Giorgio Agamben: A Critical Introduction (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2009),  248. See 268-272 for a good summary of the various critical responses to the book.

[ii] Ibid., 271-272.

[iii] Neil Levi and Michael Rothberg, “Auschwitz and the Remains of Theory: Toward an Ethics of the Borderland,” Symplokē 11.1 (2003), 29.

[iv] Nicholas Chare, “The Gap in Context: Giorgio Agamben’s ‘Remnants of Auschwitz,’” Cultural Critique 64 (2004), 61.

[v] Catherine Mills, The Philosophy of Agamben (Ithaca: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2008), 87.

[vi] J. M. Bernstein, “Bare Life, Bearing Witness: Auschwitz and the Pornography of Horror,” Parallax 10.1 (2004), 3.

[vii] Ibid., 10, 12.