June 12, 2012

De La Torre, Latina/o Social Ethics (Part 2/2)


De La Torre is absolutely correct that powerlessness is the only possible starting point for a new ethics, since, as De La Torre has already established in the first chapter, an ethics of power can only lead to devastating essentialisms and “complicity with empire” (31). That chapter, titled “The Need to Move Beyond Eurocentric Ethics,” will be the focus of my discussion for the rest of this review, and I will argue that it contains several valuable insights into the concealed operations of regulation and control in academic and political discourse.

Eurocentric ethics could be defined as any mode of moral discourse that is produced by the dominant culture and, concomitantly, privileges that culture—whether this privileging is intentional or not does not affect the exclusionary consequences and is therefore irrelevant for De La Torre’s investigation. De La Torre identifies such ideological bias in three figures: Walter Rauschenbusch, Reinhold Niebuhr, and Stanley Hauerwas. If anything is surprising about De La Torre’s reading of these authors, it is how little “digging” he had to do to locate the instances of ethnic elitism and reactionary politics in their work. De La Torre argues that Eurocentric ethics is characterized by covert rationalizations of the normalizing function of state and law, which is expressed in these three authors in various ways. Thus, despite his progressive, socialist leanings, the only way Rauschenbusch could imagine the betterment of minority communities is as a result of their uncritical, wholesale adoption of “white” attitudes, customs, and culture. Similarly, Niebuhr’s “realism” signifies a sort of defeatist pragmatism that systematically excluded from its consideration the reality of the oppressed.

On this evidence, one must conclude that it would be ethically and intellectually indefensible to employ uncritically the paradigms of these thinkers. In fact, the only problem with De La Torre’s critique of such figures as Rauschenbusch and Niebuhr is that few if any serious ethicists in the academy today would build on the ground laid by these thinkers, for whom ethics, after all, was merely a channel for them to transmit their theological concerns. However, even though De La Torre’s discussion would be much more incisive and relevant if he could find examples from contemporary ethics—for instance, in human rights discourse one often finds both a rationalization of state power and the totalization of cultural or ethnic particularities—De La Torre’s critique of Eurocentric ethics is not dulled by his perhaps inappropriate selection of these three twentieth century thinkers.

This chapter of De La Torre’s book has its most immediate and important implications for the classroom. The public school system largely ignores the significant contributions to ethics, to science, to history that minority groups and non-European cultures have made—this is perhaps especially true when it comes to contributions made by Latina/os, despite the rapid growth of the Hispanic population in the United States. And not only the public school system, but in the university, too, the historical discipline, which is itself a construct of the modern West, implicitly asks students to identify with “the winners,” while engagement with contemporary issues constantly seeks a normative position from which other positions can be judged. Such rhetorical gestures aim at “cleaning up” the messy playing field of epistemological ethics, and any approach to ethics that seeks order is complicit with the state and therefore anathema to De La Torre’s “vulgar, earthy way of doing ethics” (122). Education, therefore, must engage with marginalized voices by asking the students to read history from the perspective of “the losers,” and it must also resist the perennial temptation to simplify, to reduce, to categorize. Our future and our liberation depend on the messiness that will result from an ethics and a pedagogy para joder.

De La Torre’s ethics carries within it the radical capacity to overturn the established order. It is fitting, then, that an instrument used to deprive marginalized people of a voice will now be used exclusively as a means to force those in power to hear the powerless speak. Even so, De La Torre does not dispense with the ethical paradigms of the modern West, nor does he attempt to wipe away the residue of the Enlightenment, inasmuch as such a project, as Foucault too has shown, is impossible. Most significantly, this book succeeds instead at redrawing the boundaries and re-centering the discursive space in which ethics are constructed and practiced. It is therefore a welcome contribution to the collaborative construction of a multicultural resistance to the injustices of state power and world capitalism.